Aristotle's Principle of Non-Contradiction

Jean-Louis Hudry

Institute of Philosophy
University of Neuchâtel, Switzerland


In Metaphysics Gamma, Aristotle understands the principle of non-contradiction (PNC) as the most certain principle of all such that it is impossible to be mistaken about it. Yet, Aristotle is also concerned with the fact that some people may reject this principle. In that respect, he constructs arguments aiming to defend PNC as a true opinion. There is then a difficult contrast to explain: on the one hand, PNC is a necessary principle of the highest importance; on the other, it is merely justified as a true opinion against those who challenge it. So the essential question is as follows: if PNC is postulated as the most certain principle of all, why does Aristotle feel the need to speak of it as a mere opinion?

Many have been puzzled by this contrast. Łukasiewicz (1910) concludes about Aristotle: “he may himself have felt the weakness of his arguments; and that may have led him to present his Law as an ultimate axiom—an unassailable dogma” (p. 62, original emphases). Others have used Aristotle’s weak and problematic arguments as a way to illustrate the failure of PNC (Priest, 2006).

These reactions show that Aristotle’s defence of PNC is, at worst, not understood or, at best, not taken seriously. The aim of this tutorial will be to answer this concern by accounting for Aristotle’s method. We shall explain why PNC is defendable only as a true opinion, even though it is said to be the most certain principle of all, and we shall conclude that Aristotle’s weak defence of PNC is perfectly compatible with the postulate of PNC as a strong axiom.

Quote of Aristotle's Metaphysics

Everybody is welcome to join, and there are no specific prerequisites. The tutorial will be divided into three sessions.

I. Aristotle’s PNC and Łukasiewicz’s formulations
A first session will focus on Aristotle’s definition of PNC, as it is exclusively based on predicates and requires two conditions, namely simultaneity and similarity. PNC is also to be distinguished from two derived principles, namely the excluded middle and bivalence. Finally, contradiction is more than mere contrariness, in so far as two contraries are contradictory, if and only if one is true and the other false. We shall then compare Aristotle’s PNC with Łukasiewicz’s (1910) interpretations of it through an ontological, a logical, and a psychological formulation. Influenced by Frege's logical formalism, Łukasiewicz then accuses Aristotle of “logicism in psychology”.
 


Photo Jean-Louis Hudry

II. An Aristotelian contextualization of PNC
In a second session, we shall analyze the context in which Aristotle’s PNC takes place. Metaphysics Gamma introduces a hierarchy of sciences: philosophy is the universal science, which includes the particular sciences of physics and mathematics. Aristotle assesses PNC with respect to philosophy, in so far as PNC is a necessary principle only for those who know about the general nature of things, and which goes beyond any specific mathematical or physical nature. It is within this epistemic context that Aristotle’s PNC has to be understood, meaning that non-philosophers express an opinion about it, without being knowledgeable about its necessity. As such, the definition of Aristotle’s PNC is inseparable from the way PNC is either intrinsically cognized or merely believed.

III. Aristotle on the rejection of PNC
A third session will study why Aristotle explicitly admits the possibility of rejecting PNC. Indeed, he has to convince all non-philosophers that PNC should not be regarded as a false opinion. According to him, there are two ways of challenging PNC. One is for physicists to assume that things are endlessly changing, making their meanings indefinite and thereby irrelevant to PNC. Aristotle’s reply is that physical motion cannot be used against the postulate that things have definite meanings. The other objection is that any proof of PNC already uses PNC in the premises of the proof. Aristotle acknowledges this petitio principii, and then concludes to the absence of a direct proof. Nevertheless, he suggests an indirect refutation to this objection, aiming to show that it is impossible not to use PNC in language; thus, even the rejection of PNC will have to rely on the use of PNC.

Bibliography
Barnes, J. ‘The Law of Contradiction’, Philosophical Quarterly 19,
     302-09, 1969.

Cohen, S. M. ‘Aristotle on the Principle of Non-Contradiction’,
     Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16, 359-70, 1986.
Hudry, J.-L. ‘Aristotle on Meaning’, Archiv für Geschichte der
     Philosophie
93, 253-80, 2011.
Hudry, J.-L. ‘Aristotle on Deduction and Inferential Necessity’,
     Review of Metaphysics
67, 3-30, 2013.
Hudry, J.-L. ‘Aristotle on Modality and Predicative Necessity’,
     International Philosophical Quarterly
53, 5-21, 2013.
Hudry, J.-L. ‘Aristotle on Non-Contradiction: Philosophers vs.
     Non-Philosophers’, Journal of Ancient Philosophy 7, 51-74, 2013.
Kirwan, C. Aristotle’s Metaphysics: Books Gamma, Delta, and
     Epsilon
. Clarendon Press, 1993.
Łukasiewicz, J. ‘Aristotle on the Law of Contradiction’ In Articles on
     Aristotle: Metaphysics
. Barnes, Schofield, and Sorabji (eds.).
     Duckworth, 1910/1979.
Priest, G. Doubt Truth to be a Liar. Oxford University Press, 2006.
Wedin, M. ‘Some Logical Problems in Metaphysics Gamma’, Oxford
     Studies in Ancient Philosophy
19, 113-62, 2000.
Wians, W. ‘The Philosopher’s Knowledge of Non-Contradiction’,
     Ancient Philosophy
26, 333-53, 2006.